In the past couple posts, I've mentioned Jonathan Haidt's
Social Intuitionist Model quite a bit.
Intuitions dominate our initial moral impressions and rather than
correcting these intuitions, our faculty of reason makes these impressions
stronger. As Haidt puts it, "Reason
is the press-secretary of the intuitions, and can pretend to no other office
than that of ex-post facto spin doctor."
Perhaps the most intriguing support for this model is what Haidt calls
"moral dumbfounding," which will be the subject of this post.
To test his model,
Haidt had 30 college students answer questions about a series of dilemmas. One was a dilemma well known in the history
of moral psychology, the "Heinz dilemma." Here's the dilemma in full.
In Europe, a woman was near death from a very bad disease, a special kind of cancer. There was one drug that the doctors thought might save her. It was a form of radium for which a druggist was charging ten times what the drug cost him to make. The sick woman's husband, Heinz, went to everyone he knew to borrow the money, but he could only get together about half of what it cost. He told the druggist that his wife was dying, and asked him to sell it cheaper or let him pay later. But the druggist said, "No, I discovered the drug and I'm going to make money from it." So, Heinz got desperate and broke into the man's store to steal the drug for his wife. Was there anything wrong with what he did?
Given that this
dilemma involves explicit tradeoffs between competing interests, Haidt
predicted that people would easily engage in dispassionate moral reasoning.
As a comparison for
the Heinz dilemma, participants were presented with two other dilemmas that
didn't exhibit any obvious harm to any character. The more famous of these stories is now known
simply as "the Mark and Julie dilemma."
Julie and Mark, who are brother and sister are traveling together in France. They are both on summer vacation from college. One night they are staying alone in a cabin near the beach. They decide that it would be interesting and fun if they tried making love. At very least it would be a new experience for each of them. Julie was already taking birth control pills, but Mark uses a condom too, just to be safe. They both enjoy it, but they decide not to do it again. They keep that night as a special secret between them, which makes them feel even closer to each other. So what do you think about this? Was it wrong for them to have sex?
Participants were
also presented with a dilemma in which a medical student, Jennifer, eats a bit
of a cadaver's flesh. This cadaver was
going to be incinerated the next day, so no one would miss it. It was expected that participants would
quickly and intuitively recognize the wrongness of Mark and Julie's actions as
well as Jennifer's actions. However,
they would be at pains to verbally explain exactly why these characters had
done something wrong.
Finally,
participants were presented with two tasks that were expected to elicit strong
intuitions, though they were non-moral in nature. In one task, participants were asked to drink
a glass of juice both before and after a sterilized cockroach had been dipped
in it. The other task involved the
participants signing their name on a piece of paper. On this paper, were the words "I, (participant's
name), hereby sell my soul, after my death, to [the experimenter], for the sum
of two dollars." At the bottom of
the page was a note that read: "This is NOT a legal or binding contract,
in any way." Despite the apparent
harmlessness of each of these actions, participants were unsurprisingly
uncomfortable with these tasks.
After the
participant read each dilemma and gave their judgment, an experimenter would
"argue" with the participants.
The experimenter would non-aggressively undermine whatever reason the
participant put forth in support of their judgment. For example, if a participant said that Mark
and Julie did something wrong because they might have a deformed child, the
experimenter would remind the participant that Julie was taking birth control
pills and Mark used a condom. If the
participant said that what Heinz did was ok because his wife needed it to
survive, the experimenter would ask if it would be ok to steal if a stranger
needed it or if a beloved pet dog needed it.
The same procedure was followed for the two behavioral tasks the
participants were asked to perform. If a
participant chose not to drink the cockroach-dipped-juice, the experimenter
would remind them that the roach was sterile.
If a participant refused to sign the piece of paper, the experimenter
would remind them that it wasn't a real contract.
While participants
were going through the rigmarole of this experiment, Haidt was recording their
verbal and nonverbal responses.
Afterwards, Haidt had participants fill out a self-report survey asking
them how confident they were in their judgments, how confused they were, how
irritated they were, how much they had changed their mind from their initial
judgment, how much their judgment was based on gut feelings, and how much their
judgment was based on reason.
Haidt found striking
differences between the Heinz dilemma and the other dilemmas. When responding to the Heinz dilemma,
participants tended to provide reasons before announcing their judgment. They reported that their judgments were based
more on reason than on gut feelings.
Their judgments were relatively stable and held with high confidence. And they rarely said that they couldn't
explain their judgments. The other
dilemmas left participants in a much different mental state. Participants reported being more confused and
less confident in their judgments. They
relied more on their gut than on their reasoning; after gentle probing from the
experimenter, participants dropped most of the arguments they put forward, and
they frequently admitted that they couldn't find any reasons for their
judgments. This observation, in
particular, is what Haidt calls "moral dumbfounding." Participants maintained their judgments
despite the inability to articulate their reasons. They were, in a sense, struck speechless, or
dumbfounded. Furthermore, participants
often verbally expressed their dumbfoundedness.
These verbal expressions were made 38 times in response to the incest
story but only twice in response to the Heinz dilemma. Participants' responses to the behavioral
tasks provided a mixed bag of results but were similar to the Mark and Julie
dilemma in several respects. Participants
were unconfident in their decision not to sign the piece of paper, and they
didn't believe their decision was the result of rational deliberation. And they often said they couldn't think of
any reason, but they maintained their decision nonetheless.
Prior to this study,
moral psychologists had almost exclusively presented participants with just the
Heinz dilemma. Consequently,
psychologists inferred that moral judgment was largely the result of conscious
effortful reasoning. In hindsight, this
conclusion seems obviously invalid. This
is like showing people pictures of cute cats, asking them how they feel, and
inferring that humans only feel happiness.
It's odd that this was the dominant paradigm for decades. Perhaps I'm missing something, but Haidt's
insight seems like an obvious idea whose time had come. It's now quite evident that, at least under
certain circumstances, people may eschew reason in favor of their gut
instincts. Haidt's study doesn't warrant
the conclusion that the majority of moral judgment is intuitively driven, but
it does provide another brick in the wall of evidence for the Social Intuitionist Model.
Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F., & Murphy, S. (2000). Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason. Unpublished manuscript, University of Virginia.
Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F., & Murphy, S. (2000). Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason. Unpublished manuscript, University of Virginia.
No comments:
Post a Comment